- Econometrics: A Strange Process / Artikel - --- ELLI ---, 17.07.2002, 16:22
Econometrics: A Strange Process / Artikel
<font face="Verdana" size="1" color="#002864">http://www.mises.org/fullstory.asp?control=1001</font>
<font face="Verdana" color="#002864" size="5"><strong>Econometrics: A Strange Process</strong></font>
<font size="4">by Robert P. Murphy</font>
[Posted July 19, 2002]
<font size="4">[img][/img] Until
recently, most macroeconomic forecasters, assisted by mathematical models, were
predicting economic recovery and rising stock indices. But the market has
reminded us that reality doesn’t always correspond to the predictions of those
who claim the mantle of"science." As is so often the case, those
economists who were more humble in their pretensions to knowledge avoided such
embarrassment.</font>
<strong><font size="4">The Methodological Divide</font></strong>
<font size="4">The Austrian School of economics is known for its aversion to
mathematical modeling of human behavior. The neoclassical mainstream, on the
other hand, is quite fond of this approach, and uses the mathematical method for
just about any problem. I think it is fair to say that most mainstream
economists would prefer the precision of a false formal model, versus the
generality of a true verbal proposition. </font>
<font size="4">This misplaced reliance on the power of mathematical tools for
economic analysis is epitomized in the field of econometrics, which employs
statistical techniques in the study of empirical data concerning economic
phenomena. Unlike their mainstream colleagues in game theory--who are
notorious for criticizing human"players" when their actions fail to
correspond to the strategies employed in a particular game’s equilibrium
state--the econometricians believe they are exempt from the biases of a priori
theorizing. The true believer in econometrics takes no particular stand on
doctrinal questions, and rather thinks that the facts will"speak for
themselves."</font>
<font size="4">Ludwig von Mises exposed the fallacy in this supposedly
atheoretical method:</font>
<font size="4">It is true the empiricists reject [a priori] theory; they
pretend that they aim to learn only from historical experience. However, they
contradict their own principles as soon as they pass beyond the unadulterated
recording of individual single prices and begin to construct series and to
compute averages. A datum of experience and a statistical fact is only a price
paid at a definite time and a definite place for a definite quantity of a
certain commodity. The arrangement of various price data in groups and the
computation of averages are guided by theoretical deliberations which are
logically and temporally antecedent. The extent to which certain attending
features and circumstantial contingencies of the price data concerned are
taken or not taken into consideration depends on theoretical reasoning of the
same kind. Nobody is so bold as to maintain that a rise of a per cent in the
supply of any commodity must always--in every country and at any time--result
in a fall of <em>b </em>per cent in its price. But as no quantative economist
ever ventured to define precisely on the ground of statistical experience the
special conditions producing a definite deviation from the ratio <em>a</em>: <em>b</em>,
the futility of his endeavors is manifest. [Human
Action p. 351]</font>
<font size="4">Although the student of Austrian economics may share Mises’s
opinions about the dubiousness of econometrics, the fact is that he or she must
take classes and exams in this field in order to receive a degree from most
programs in the United States. In an attempt to help such students"keep
hope alive," I will now share my impressions and an anecdote gleaned from
my experience in a mandatory course in macroeconometrics.</font>
<strong><font size="4">Market Process?</font></strong>
<font size="4">Austrian economists, especially those of a Hayekian bent,
stress that the market is a process. Ironically, econometricians use the
same term, but they mean by it something completely different.</font>
<font size="4">For example, when he wishes to model the price of a particular
stock, the econometrician may say,"Assume <em>p(t) </em>follows a random
walk process." What he means is that the price at any time <em>t </em>equals
the price at time <em>t - 1</em>, plus a completely random"shock."
The shock is modeled as a random variable with mean zero and a certain variance.</font>
<font size="4">Notice already that this approach has given up on trying to
explain how real-world prices are actually formed. In reality, today’s
prices have no causal connection with tomorrow’s prices. Every day, the price
of a stock is formed afresh by decisions on the part of investors to buy or sell.
The stock price today seems to be partially"dependent" on the stock
price yesterday only because the underlying factors that caused yesterday’s
price are largely the same today. The case of a stock price is completely
different from, say, the balance of one’s bank account, which does remain
constant from day to day, except for"autoregressive" changes due to
interest compounding, or"shocks" due to deposits and withdrawals.</font>
<font size="4">The econometric approach to stock price movements is analogous
to a meteorologist who looks for correlations between various measurements of
atmospheric conditions. For example, he might find that the temperature on
any given day is a very good predictor of the temperature on the following day. But
no meteorologist would believe that the reading on the thermometer one day
somehow caused the reading the next day; he knows that the correlation is due to
the fact that the true causal factors--such as the angle of the earth relative
to its orbital plane around the sun--do not change much from one day to the next.</font>
<font size="4">Unfortunately, this distinction between causation and
correlation is not stressed in econometrics. Indeed, for economists truly
committed to the positive method, there can be no such distinction. Although
the econometric pioneers may understand why certain assumptions are made and can
offer a priori justifications such as"rational expectations" for the
details of a particular model, the students of such pioneers are often caught up
in the mathematical technicalities and lose sight of the true causes of economic
phenomena.</font>
<strong><font size="4">A Case in Point</font></strong>
<font size="4">Lest the reader feel I am speaking in broad generalities, let
me offer as an example a question that was on one of my exams. The question
epitomizes the problems with the econometric approach of stipulating a
particular"process" that generates the observed levels of some
variable:</font>
<font size="4">Suppose we have <em>T</em> observations on the time series <em>x(t)</em>,
which has mean <em>μ</em>. Suppose also that <em>d(t)</em>, the
deviation of <em>x(t)</em> from its sample average<em> s</em>, which is
defined as <em>d(t) <span class="613341113-17072002">==</span> x(t) - s</em>,
follows an AR(1) process, that is, <em>d(t) = ρd(t - </em>1<em>) + e(t).</em>
What is the variance of the sample average, <em>s</em>?</font>
<font size="4">As I sat staring at this question, I was absolutely befuddled,
since I believe it makes no sense. My problem was not that such a question was
of little use in understanding the business cycle or the stock market; my
problem was that I believe its propositions are contradictory.</font>
<font size="4">The question assumes that there is some variable <em>x(t)</em>,
the true mean of which is <em>μ</em>. That is, if we took the mean of
all realizations of<em> x(t)</em> from <em>t = 1</em> to <em>t = ∞</em>,
the result would be<em> μ</em>. In practice, however, we never have an
infinite number of realizations to analyze, but only a finite number <em>T</em>
of sample observations. Although we can’t know the true mean<em> μ</em>,
we can calculate<em> s</em>, which is the sample average, or mean of the
observations >from <em>x(</em>1<em>) </em>to<em> x(T).</em></font>
<font size="4">Now, the exam question above wasn’t intended to be"deep";
I suspect that talking about an autoregressive (AR) process concerning the
variable <em>d(t)</em> was an indirect way to get the student to assume that <em>x(t)</em>
itself followed an AR(1) process, and to then apply a standard formula to"compute
the sample variance of the mean of <em>T</em> realizations >from an
autocorrelated time series process" (quoted from the solution later given
by my professor).</font>
<font size="4">An autoregressive process is one in which the value <em>t </em>is
dependent on some fraction of the value at <em>t - </em>1, plus a random"error"
term of mean zero. For example, we might have <em>x(t) = </em>.5 <em>* x(t
-</em> 1<em>) + e(t)</em>, which means that the value of <em>x</em> at time t is
equal to one-half its value at time <em>t - </em>1, plus some random error term <em>e(t)</em>
that on average will equal zero.</font>
<font size="4">It makes sense to say that <em>x(t) </em>in the above question
follows such an AR(1) process. However, the question said that the
deviation of <em>x(t)</em> from its sample average <em>s </em>follows an AR(1)
process, and this I believe is nonsensical. This is because, unlike the
infinitely long<em> x(t)</em> process--in which the deviations of <em>x(t)</em>
>from its mean<em> μ</em> can in principle sum to any number (though we
expect in the long run this sum to be zero)--for a finite sample of size <em>T, </em>the
deviations<em> d(t)</em> by definition must sum to zero. So when my
professor--following the standard econometric practice--stipulated that the
series <em>d(t)</em> followed a particular process, he stipulated the impossible.</font>
<font size="4">Let’s illustrate the problem with a sample of size <em>T=</em>3. Suppose
that the observed values of <em>x </em>are 1, 2, and 3. The sample average <em>s</em>
is thus 2. The value of <em>d(</em>1<em>) </em>is -1; that is, <em>x</em>(1<em>)
- s = </em>-1. The value of <em>d(</em>2<em>) </em>is 0, and the value
of <em>d(</em>3<em>) </em>is <em>1</em>. As must be the case, the sum of the
deviations of <em>x(t)</em> from the sample mean are zero; i.e., -1 + 0 + 1 = 0.</font>
<font size="4">Now notice that this makes it impossible for the variable<em>
d(t)</em> to follow an AR process. This is because the value of <em>d</em>(1)
and<em> d</em>(2) completely determine the value of <em>d</em>(3). Given
that<em> d</em>(1) is<em> </em>-1 and <em>d(</em>2) is 0, <em>d</em>(3) must be
1 to render the entire sum zero.</font>
<font size="4">But if this is the case, then the stipulated formula for <em>d(t)--</em>that
is, <em>d(t) = ρd(t - </em>1<em>) + e(t)--</em>cannot be true. For we
know that <em>d(</em>3<em>)</em> is not some function of <em>d(</em>2<em>) </em>plus
a completely random error term <em>e(</em>3<em>)</em>, which in principle can
take any value. So to reiterate, it’s not merely that the question is
irrelevant to a true understanding of economics; it’s rather that even on
purely mathematical terms, the question makes no sense.</font>
<strong><font size="4">The Econometrician’s Response</font></strong>
<font size="4">I emailed my concerns to my professor<a title href="http://www.mises.org/fullstory.asp?control=1001#_ftn1" name="_ftnref1">*</a>
and his teaching assistant. They told me that I was reading too much
into the question, and that my problem was of a very"philosophical"
nature. Rather than pondering what the question"meant," I should
have realized the relevant formula from the information given, and applied it to
get the answer.</font>
<font size="4">I believe their stance is typical of the mainstream approach.
It would be one thing if all of the formal rigor of modeling were followed
through to the deepest foundations of economic science. But unfortunately,
I believe that in day-to-day practice, the mainstream economist relies on
certain assumptions and techniques to address a particular problem, since he
knows"how to solve" the question when it is asked in this way.</font>
<font size="4">But surely there is something fundamentally wrong when he
persists in this method, even when the"question" so posed is
internally contradictory.</font>
<hr align="left" width="33%" SIZE="1">
Robert P. Murphy, a Rowley Fellow of the Mises Institute, is an economics
graduate student at New York University. See his Mises.org <font color="#000080">Articles
Archive</font> and send him <font color="#000080">MAIL</font>.
<hr align="left" width="33%" SIZE="1">
<div>
<div id="ftn1">
<a title href="http://www.mises.org/fullstory.asp?control=1001#_ftnref1" name="_ftn1">*</a><font size="2">
In fairness, I want to point out that my professor was a very good one. He
always responded to questions, and in fact went out of his way one lecture
to explain the dangers of confusing correlation with causation. I also
should disclose that I was inadequately prepared for the exam in question; I
do not claim that I"understand" completely the field of
macroeconometrics and have fully surveyed it and found it wanting.</font>
</div>
</div>
<center>
<HR>
</center>

gesamter Thread: