- Choice and Preference / Artikel mises.org, engl. - - ELLI -, 20.02.2003, 15:31
Choice and Preference / Artikel mises.org, engl.
--><div>
<font color="#002864" size="1" face="Verdana">http://www.mises.org/fullstory.asp?control=1163</font>
</div>
<div>
</div>
<div>
<font face="Verdana" size="2"><font color="#002864" size="5"><strong>Choice and Preference</strong></font>
</div>
<div>
<font size="4">By Gene Callahan</font>
<font size="2">[Posted February 20, 2003]</font>
<blockquote dir="ltr" style="MARGIN-RIGHT: 0px">
<font size="2">[img][/img] Choice
is choice between alternatives, and these alternatives must be
distinguishable or they are not alternatives; moreover, one must in some
way present itself as more attractive than the other, or it cannot be
chosen. -- R.G. Collingwood, The Idea of Nature, p. 41</font>
[/i]
<font size="2">Bryan Caplan, in his widely circulated web article,"</font><font size="2">Why
I Am Not an Austrian Economist</font><font size="2">," and in his
subsequent"</font><font size="2">The
Austrian Search for Realistic Foundations</font><font size="2">" in
the Southern Economic Journal, seemingly has questioned the Austrian
contention that choice implies preference. Caplan says:"One can only
observe that I choose a green sweater, but this does not rule out the
possibility that I was actually indifferent between a green sweater and a
blue sweater." The implication is that Caplan chose on the basis of
indifference, not preference, and so the Austrians are clearly wrong.</font>
<font size="2"><strong>Preference for What?</strong></font>
<font size="2">Imagine a buyer arriving at Hunt's Point produce market in
New York intent on purchasing 200 boxes of oranges. When he gets to the dock
of the fellow who has the fruit, he tells him what he wants. But rather than
immediately beginning to load the buyer's truck, the seller asks,"Which
200?"</font>
<font size="2">"Huh?" asks the buyer.</font>
<font size="2">"Well, I have roughly 2500 boxes of oranges. Which
200 do you want?"</font>
<font size="2">The buyer is flummoxed. He was expecting to buy a
standardized commodity, boxed oranges. He certainly didn't intend to spend
his time picking through 2500 boxes to find the 200 he āwants.ā He
counts on the seller to have distributed the weight and quality in a fairly
random way throughout his stock, so that it doesn't particularly matter
which 200 boxes he takes.</font>
<font size="2">We should note that the buyer is quite aware that every
orange is unique. No two oranges will have the exact same weight, shape,
coloring, or degree of ripeness. Certainly, if offered the choice between
200 boxes of rotten oranges and 200 boxes of just-picked oranges, the buyer
will choose the latter. But he knows this seller, has dealt with him before,
and is pretty sure he's not selling (many) rotten oranges. He'd just like to
get his 200 boxes and get out of there.</font>
<font size="2">Faced with this unprecedented behavior on the part of the
seller, the buyer says,"Well, give me those 200 on the left."</font>
<font size="2">Now, Bryan Caplan pops out from behind a stack of orange
boxes."A-ha," he exclaims,"you've proved the Austrians
wrong!" How will an Austrian respond?</font>
<font size="2">This Austrian will begin by noting that, for economics,
the difference between two goods does not consist in every physical
difference we might discover, but only those differences the economic agent
himself considers when deliberating his choice.</font>
<font size="2">Choice does not imply preference over all potentially
detectable physical differences between goods. For instance, I do not recall
ever picking my clothes based on the spin configuration of the electrons in
the garments in question. Nevertheless, I do, every day, pick out clothes
with some particular state of electron spin.</font>
<font size="2">But it would be absurd to attempt to draw any economic
conclusions from that fact, other than the trivial and obvious one that
electron spin is just not a factor I take into account when choosing my
wardrobe. For instance, there is no sense in claiming that we have now
determined a point on my clothes-color/electron-spin indifference curve. We
can impute preference only about the differences between goods that are subjectively
relevant to the chooser.</font>
<font size="2">When Caplan picks sweaters, he is, for economics, in no
different a position than a colorblind person who literally cannot see
the difference between green and blue sweaters. Green and blue have no more
economic relevance to his choice than electron spin do to mine.</font>
<font size="2">Considering Caplanās reported choice, we might speculate
that he picked the green sweater because it was at the top of the drawer. In
that case, the actual preference he displayed was to do as little work as
possible when retrieving a sweater to wear.</font>
<font size="2">However, if we caught Caplan pawing through his drawer,
rummaging past many blue sweaters to pull out a green one, we would question
his claim of color indifference. It would still be possible that he truly
was indifferent between green and blue sweaters. But, we would logically
insist, there was some reason he bypassed all of those other sweaters
to get the green one out from the bottom. Perhaps he knew the green sweater
was the least itchy (or the warmest, the most fashionable, the lightest,
etc.). Then we would have some preference information about Caplan:
we would know that he preferred the less itchy sweater along, even given the
cost of digging it out, to the ease of grabbing an itchier one from the top
of the drawer. But note that we have information on his preference
for one good over another, not on his indifference between two goods.</font>
<font size="2"><strong>So Where's the Beef?</strong></font>
<font size="2">However, it is not altogether clear to me how Caplan
believes he disagrees with Austrians about indifference. If he is contending
that indifference can be the basis for a choice, then I have outlined what I
believe is a sensible Austrian response. But I detect some confusion in
Caplanās view of what Austrians are saying:</font>
<blockquote dir="ltr" style="MARGIN-RIGHT: 0px">
<font size="2">"Perhaps the most basic assumption of consumer
choice theory is that given two choices a and b, an agent
can strictly prefer a to b⦠can strictly prefer
b to a⦠or be indifferent between a
and bā¦. While Mises and Rothbard accept the first two
cases of strict preferences, they argue that the third case of perfect
indifference is nonsensical because it cannot be demonstrated in action."</font>
[/i]
<font size="2">I believe Caplanās interpretation of Mises and
Rothbard is wrong here. They are not arguing that indifference is nonsensical,
in either a psychological or purely logical sense, but that it is
economically irrelevant. Furthermore, to contend that a choice took
place based on indifference is nonsensical.</font>
<font size="2">Caplan says,"The crucial assumption - shared by both
Mises and Rothbard - is that all preferences can be revealed in action."
Again, I think Caplan has gotten them wrong. The crucial assumption they
share is that only preferences revealed in action are relevant to the
economist. Those are the preferences that played a role in actual economic
activity. A psychologist or an epistemologist might have something to say
about preferences not acted on, but the economist doesn't. No Austrian of
which I am aware has ever held that the only thing going on in a
personās head during the day are his preferences as revealed in his
choices.</font>
<font size="2">Caplan continues:"For example, my preference for ice
cream at the current instant cannot be revealed, since by the time I managed
to find an ice cream vendor the current instant would have passed. Buying
ice cream ten minutes from now only reveals a preference for ice cream <em>then</em>.".</font>
<font size="2">But that is false. Caplan's preference for ice cream at
"the current instant" is revealed by his undertaking (or not) a
plan of action intended to procure ice cream. All action is oriented
toward future satisfactions, as all plans take time to reach fruition. Even
if Caplan never discovers an ice cream vendor, the economist could say
something about his preferences merely from the fact he undertook the search,
just as an economist could discern something about my preferences if I set
out to become the strongest man in the world, even if I never succeed.</font>
<font size="2">If Caplan doesn't get up to go get a scoop, the economist still
can say something about his ice cream preference: either Caplan contemplated
a plan to get some ice cream but preferred whatever he was doing at his desk,
or he never even considered ice cream during the time in question. (And here
we can see the basis for Kirznerian entrepreneurship: In the latter case, it
may be that Caplan would have preferred eating ice cream over any other
possible activity at that moment, if only he had thought of it. The
sudden awareness of a previously undetected opportunity for profit is the
essence of Kirznerās idea of the entrepreneur.)</font>
<font size="2">However, if all Caplan means is that in some psychological
sense indifference can be said to exist, then there is nothing
contra-Austrian in that contention. Beginning with Carl Menger, what
Austrians have held is that indifference cannot be the basis for economic
activity. Caplan may very well, as he says,"know some cases in which
[he is] indifferent." I merely contend that there is no case in which
he was indifferent and chose based on that indifference."I am
often indifferent between the colors of clothes," Caplan says, and we
can grant him that, while insisting that simply means that he is not
choosing clothes based on their color, and color will not enter into an
economic description of his choice at all.</font>
<font size="2">Caplan says,"[T]hough I pick one color, I know that
I would have picked the other if the prices were not equal."
Caplan apparently wants to claim that he is at a point on his"color
indifference curve." But if the prices of the sweaters were not equal,
color would still be irrelevant to his choice. He would be picking
the blue sweater based on its lower price, not its lovely hue. For Caplan,
finding otherwise identical blue and green sweaters priced at $40 and $50 is
the same as my finding identical blue sweaters priced at $40 and $50. Caplan
is in the same position in regards to sweater color as most people are in
regards, for instance, to the ultrasonic characteristics of a symphony
recording.</font>
<font size="2"><strong>Austrians and Common Sense</strong></font>
<font size="2">Caplan makes one more claim, which, while tangential to my
main argument, I want to briefly address:</font>
<blockquote dir="ltr" style="MARGIN-RIGHT: 0px">
<font size="2">"The implication [in the response of various
Austrians to Caplan's original article] is that Austrian claims and common
sense often really are at odds. Austrians must in consequence say that
they are right and common sense is wrong. In spite of disclaimers to the
contrary, I believe that this is the real Austrian position" (</font><font size="2">Probability,
Common Sense, and Realism: A Reply to Hülsmann and Block</font><font size="2">,
also available here.)</font>
[/i]
<font size="2">I do not wish to enter in depth into the dispute between
Thomas Reid and Immanuel Kant, which Caplan cites, except to note that
Reid's"common-sense" position is a sort of anti-philosophy, which
can be used to prove that the Earth is flat, maggots grow from rotting meat,
and the stars are all set in a dark blue bowl resting upside down atop the
Earth. It is basically an admonition to concentrate hard on the shadows on
the cave wall, and ignore that voice behind you tempting you to turn around
and look toward the light.</font>
<font size="2">Nevertheless, in the case of indifference, common sense is
firmly on the Austrian side. The"man on the street," watching
someone else order steak instead of chicken and then asked whether the diner,
at that moment, preferred steak or chicken, would invariably answer"steak."
As one āman on the streetā (who happens to be a woman), Elizabeth
Bernard, wrote to me:</font>
<font color="black" size="2">"[When responding to the computer
prompt āPress any key to continue,ā] it seems to me here that the [revealed]
preference is not which key to strike, but whether one wants to
continue, or notā¦. The choice is whether to strike or not, not which
key to strike. Myself, I always just throw my hands on the keyboard in a
slapdash way to choose any key" (private e-mail).</font>
<font size="2"><strong>Should Indifference Curves Be Banished?</strong></font>
<font size="2">Iād like to close by noting that there is nothing
objectionable, as far as I can see, in the mere notion of indifference
curves. Here, some Austrians may part ways with me. The bone of contention
will be whether a model, to be of any use, must be āessentiallyā
realistic, or whether an admittedly unrealistic model may have its purposes.
I hold that, so long as we donāt forget the unrealistic assumptions we
have made, we are free to make what models we will and then see what insight,
if any, they yield.</font>
<font size="2">Indifferences curves depict the limit of a process in
which we have assumed:</font>
<ul>
~ <font size="2">all goods can be divided into arbitrarily small units;</font>
~ <font size="2">humans take such infinitesimal amounts into
consideration when choosing; and</font>
~ <font size="2">the transaction costs in any exchange can be made
arbitrarily small. </font></li>
</ul>
<font size="2">If we keep the above (admittedly unrealistic) assumptions
in mind then indifference curves can be used in much the same way as other
limit constructs. However, they bear only a distant, very abstract
resemblance to real economic activity. Not only are goods not perfectly
divisible physically, but human considerations when choosing are even
lumpier. When picking breakfast, I typically might choose between having two
eggs or a bowl of cereal. The fact that if I were a preference-maximizing
computer I would choose 1.0374 eggs and.462 bowls of cereal has only a
remote bearing on what I will have for breakfast.</font>
<hr align="left" width="33%" SIZE="1">
<font size="2">Gene Callahan, who writes frequently for Mises.org, is
author of <font color="#000080" size="2">Economics
for Real People</font> from the Mises Institute. See his
Mises.org <font color="#000080" size="2">Articles
Archive</font> and send him <font color="#000080" size="2">MAIL</font>.
His book is available through Mises.org or Amazon.com.
Read more about Callahan's book at Economics
for Real People.</font>
<font size="2"><strong>References</strong></font>
<font size="2">Bryan
Caplan's economics page, containing the papers mentioned above.</font>
<font size="2">Collingwood, R.G. (1960 [1945]) The Idea of Nature,
Oxford University Press: London.</font>
</div>
</font>

gesamter Thread: